Biljana Percinkova, Charles Berner, Marika Apostolova, Taxhedin Selimi: SELF-REFERENCED SYSTEMS IN ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE AND QUANTUM PHYSICS; RADICAL THEORY AND APPLICATION

ABSTRACT:

      Deep analysis of the barriers in Artificial Intelligence and Robotics based on Goedel's Law of Incompleteness will be given by introducing propositional calculus, typographical number theory and building formal logical systems. Mathematical proofs of consistence and completeness of formal logical systems (or simply robots in artificial intelligence) will be analyzed by pointing out the limitations of the contemporary approach and a radical theory offering resolution will be presented. Interpretations of quantum physics will be analyzed step by step as in the diagram presented and solution based on a radical theory will be offered. Strong support in terms of comparison of the results with the measurements of relevant parameters of particle physics done in the Institute for particle Physics Research in CERN, Geneva, will be clearly presented and mathematical proofs offered.


Picture 1

      The theory proposed is a 'non dualist' resolution (to the consciousness/observer problem in quantum physics and completeness problem in artificial intelligence) as defined by Jonathan Shear (1997), which states that rather than conscious experience being generated from the physical world, or the physical world being a product of conscious experience - both are considered to be aspects of a deeper fundamental reality. Each individual's state of conscious experience is a real state had by a real entity, and that which that conscious state is of is also real - in that it is based on those same real entities. The subjective state and its object arise inextricably linked from that which underlies them which is a finite set of agents and their acts of choices. The underlying mathematics is based on random directed graphs and matrices.

       After the limitations and pitfalls of contemporary approaches known in artificial intelligence and quantum physics will be given, the results obtained by the Radical theory will be computed by computer programs and comparisons with measurements offered. Monte Carlo simulation method will be applied for simulating the behavior of the agents and their connections in complex networks. Validation of the simulation model offered will be provided.

INTRODUCTION

    It is unlikely that the problem of understanding what subjective conscious experience is can be solved unless, as suggested by Roger Penrose (1996), there are "important changes in our picture of physical reality". Even more definitively Penrose says,
"I certainly do not expect to find any answers [about mind, consciousness, space-time, etc.] in sub-atomic physics, for example. What I am arguing for is a radical upheaval in the very basis of physical theory."
That is to say, without a theory that upsets the standard paradigm of science we may not be able to understand the relation of first person conscious experience to the physical world.

        Resolution of Goedel's theorem of non completeness is also provided by the new Paradigm.

     The theory proposed here by Charles Berner and mathematically supported by Biljana Percinkova is a 'non dualist' resolution to the consciousness/observer problem as defined by Jonathan Shear (1997) which states that rather than conscious experience being generated from the physical world, or the physical world being a product of conscious experience, both are considered to be aspects of a deeper fundamental reality. Each individual's state of conscious experience is a real state had by a real entity, and that which that conscious state is of is also real, in that it is based on those same real entities. The subjective state and its object arise inextricably linked from that which underlies them. The present form of the theory was inspired by John Wheeler's (1990) suggestion that information is fundamental to the physics of the universe and by David Chalmers' (1995) speculation that information may be "truly fundamental" with "two basic aspects, corresponding to the physical and the phenomenal features of the world." Wheeler also states (1979) that that on which the laws of physics are based cannot also be physical, and Chalmers argues (1996) that conscious experience must be nonphysical.

An Overview of the Theory

        We propose that the fundamental reality that underlies both the physical world and conscious experience is a number

1 of nonphysical agents.
2 each agent has three qualities:

(i)  intrinsic uniqueness, or 'whoness' (the agent is itself and not any other agent);
(ii)  individual initiative, or ability and,
(iii) existence.

      The first two qualities are agent specific, and the last is common to all agents.


Diagram 1

        The common existence of unique agents can be thought of in at least three other ways:

(1) All of the agents make up a single realm of existence.

(2) Each agent is in as many states as there are agents, each of those states being a state of (nonphysical) relation to a different agent, in other words, any one of an agent's states is a first person relation with some particular agent.

 (3) Each agent is in as many states as there are agents, each of those states being informed by a different agent; in other words, the content of any one of an agent's states is information based on some particular agent.

Hypothesis or research questions

        The basic hypothesis is that the Information (or Lila Paradigm) could give us the total number of non physical agents as well as some basic parameters known in particle physics.

          The derivation of the number of existing nonphysical agents (N).

          The value for N that produces computations of values for our physical Universe that agree most closely with measured values is (10e)π (10 to the e to the π ); however, this is also the value that has the weakest explanation for it. As shown below, e and π are the result of two different progressions of embedded bifurcated sub-states in a giant circuit system, and it may be that there is a third major progression based on 10 (Arneodo 1992). To show how π and e are intertwined, both π and e are described in terms of the information paradigm. We begin by writing the standard formula for π:1 

π = the sum of

the limit N à ∞ [6(1/12 + 1/22 + 1/32 + . . . + 1/N2)]½

where N is any whole number. There are many agents out of the 1023 agents that have arrows extending across the circuit to most, if not all, of the agents in the giant circuit arrangement. Although in Diagram 4b only four arrows are shown extending from agent I, consider agent I to be one of those agents. In the information paradigm, the value of π varies from the early universe to the present, and the value is proportional to the following formula based on the standard formula.

 a/b1+ a/b2 + a/b3 +. . .+ a/bN

       The square, the square root and the 6 are ignored here as they are constant for every term and thus do not affect the proportionality.

     The numerator in all of the terms is the conscious sub-state produced by the 'single' circuit arrow of common time, represented by IàF . This sub-state, being the irreducible basis of the agents' consciousness of a common world, counts as one, 1. The denominator, conscious sub-state b1, is produced by the sub arrangement IàO and also counts as 1 because it is also irreducible, in that it has no sub-states. Because both conscious sub-states a and b1 are embedded in the bifurcated 1st term sub-state of consciousness, produced from the arrangement:

they are compared (placed in ratio relative to each other) as a/b1 which is 1/1, the first term of the standard formula.

      The 2nd term in the proportional formulation has the denominator b2, which has two cross-over arrows in it, IàO and IàZ , each of which produces an irreducible sub-state of consciousness and, therefore, counts as one. Because IàO and IàZ each combine to produce sub states of consciousness that are embedded in sub-state b2, these sub-states of consciousness are thereby in a single state of consciousness where those sub-states are added and so count as 2, that is, as 1 + 1 together. Because both sub-states a and b2 are in the bifurcated 2nd term sub-state, they are compared as the ratio a/b2, which is, therefore, 1/2, the second term in the standard formula.

The 3rd. term denominator, b3: has three cross-over arrows in it and for the same reasons that the 2nd term has a ratio of 1/2, the 3rd term has a ratio of 1/3, which is the 3rd term of the standard formula. And so on to N terms, which, in this case, are finite in number. All of the terms are summed in the consciousness of each agent in the circuit due to all the sub-states of consciousness that are the different terms being in the single, overall state of consciousness which is produced by the entire arrangement symbolized in Diagram 4b.

The usual formula for e is:

e = the sum

limit Nà∞ (1/1! + 1/1! + 1/2! + 1/3! +. . .+ 1/N!)

where N is any whole number. The number e is found in a particular combination of sub-states in the circuit arrangement. Refer to Diagram 4b in the following. The proportional formula for e is:

 a/a' + a/c1 + a/c2 + a/c3 +. . .+ a/cN

        The 1st term numerator, produced by the arrangement I à F, which is an irreducible sub-state of consciousness, and thus has a value of 1, is called sub-state a. The denominator is sub-state a', which is the sub-state produced by the entire circuit, including an iteration of I à F. Such a linear arrangement of a single state of consciousness has a value of 1 multiplied by 1, which is 1!. Since both a and a' are in the overall state (the entirety of Diagram 4b) they are (linearly) compared, as a/a', which is 1/1!, the first term of the standard formula.

        The 2nd term numerator is also I à F, sub-state a, which is 1; however, the denominator is any one of the possible bifurcations extending from agent I, which are:

        Bifurcation No. 2. is used in the 2nd term example. The sub-state of consciousness produced from it is called sub-state c1, shown in the next diagram embedded in the 2nd term, along with sub-state a:

2nd term sub-state a/c1 = 1/1!

       The bifurcated sub-state cl has the numerical value of 1 • 1 because there are two single states of consciousness embedded in it, those produced by I à F and by I à O. Both sub-state a and sub-state c1 are embedded in the bifurcated 2nd term sub-state and are thereby compared in the ratio a/c1, which is 1/1!, the 2nd term of the standard formula.

     In the third term, the numerator is 1, for the same reasons as above, as in all the terms. The denominator, the sub-state c2, however, has two bifurcated arrangements in it, cla and clb each producing a separate state of consciousness:

 3rd term sub-state a/c2 = 1/1 • 2 = 1/2!

       The two sub-states cla and clb are embedded in sub-state c2 and, since c2 is a single state of consciousness, those two sub-states are thereby added and count as 2; and in sub-state c2 the two sub-states, each of which is 1, combine as 1 x 1 and also combine with sub-state c2 as 1 x 1 x 2, which is the factorized term 2!. Also, c2 is embedded along with sub-state a in the 3rd term sub-state, comparing them in the ratio a/c2, which is the ratio 1/2!, the 3rd term of the standard formula.

For the same reasons as above, the fourth term is a/c3:

4th term sub-state a/c3 = 1/3!

        There are three c2 consciousness sub-states each of which is made up of two cl sub-states embedded in a c3 sub-state, which, therefore, has the factorization of 1 x 2 x 3 = 3!, the 4th term of the standard formula; and, so on through the rest of the finite number (N) of terms. Again, these are summed due to all the terms being part of the single state of consciousness of the entire arrangement in Diagram 4b.

       The number π is based on the ratio of the number of cross-over arrows in a sub-state to the arrow in the circuit from a single agent in the circuit, while e is based on the ratio of the number of bifurcations in a sub state to the arrow from a single agent in the circuit. As can be seen, the same arrows embedded in different groupings of sub-states produce both π and e. The numeric consequence of this for a finite N is proportional to e π .

       Using the values of e and π as computed from the standard formulas,  where  N  is  equal  to  infinity, a  close approximation  to  the  number of  agents  in  our  Universe  can  be  computed from N = (10e)π . Using base 10 values for e and π in the Mathematica program, the result is:

138,258,752,126,535,254,782,246.6528....

      This should probably be rounded down to 6 in the last place before the decimal because the actual N is finite and a whole number, whereas the Mathematica computations of e and π and were made assuming that N is infinite. In the computations throughout this paper, we use N as equal to 1.382587521 x 1023.

      It is obvious that π should be involved with spatial and, therefore, all energy phenomena, because the very bifurcations that produce space are the same as those which produce the π ratio. This also applies to e, though the effect is less widely spread.

       Three less precise derivations of N follow to provide a check on the assumption that (10e)π is the relationship that produces the real value of N.

       The point of inflection of the inflationary curve was estimated by the New Inflationary Theory (Guth 1984) at about 6 x 10-33sec. A later (Guth 1997) estimate is about 10-34sec. Due to many parameters being guessed at in the theory, the time of inflection could vary from about 10-35sec to about 10-31sec.

      The information model formula for the point of inflection is given by π /2 N tq (see Section VII), so tq.

       According to this, N is about 3 x 1022, using the 1984 estimate; however, this could vary from 6 x 1019 for the 10-35sec estimate, to about 5.5 x 1023 for the 10-31sec estimate.

      Using the rest mass formulas for two leptons pairs, each of which contains N in the formula, and using the best measured values for the rest masses of equivalent leptons from those pairs, a value for N can be found. 2M(5)/M(3) is the ratio of rest mass numbers of the tau-anti-tau pair and the electron-positron pair, where

 M(5)  is  (120 N4)1/5 and M(3) is (6 N2

       The best measured value for the tau particle/electron ratio is 3491ฑ6 (Perl 1990). Using this value to solve the equation,

3491 = 2(120 N4)/(6 N3) for N; then, N = (3/219/2 53/2) 3491, which is 1.3836 x 1023 (ฑ~0.002).

This compares to the N = (10e)π value of 1.3826...X 1023, a difference of about +0.07%.

       The formula for the Compton wavelength of the electron (λce) is eฑKn. Using the best measurement of the elementary charge, eฑ, expressed as length (Misner 1973), 1.38114132 x 10-34 cm; and, the formula for n = NN/ eK. Then λce = eฑ K (N-N/eK), and solving for N gives

= 1.382587517 x 1023, where λce is 2.42531058 x 10-14cm (Cohen 1990).

This is different from (10e)π by about -3 x 10-7%.

        Given the closeness of the correlations, the assumption in a. above, while not carefully supported by logic, nevertheless seems likely to be correct and, therefore, the value for N derived there is likely to be the number of nonphysical agents that exist.

 

Universal Physical Constants c, h, and G

        Using the values derived in appendices A and B, new standard values of the universal physical constants, c, h, and G can be easily calculated to much greater accuracies. The calculated value of G constitutes a prediction that is likely to be tested by measurements in the coming decade.

       The speed of light, c is which is equal to 2.99792458 x 1010 cm/sec, which compares to the currently measured value of 2.92792458 x 1010cm/sec.

    The value of Planck's reduced constant (ħ), expressed as length squared, is 1p2, which is

2.61403186 x10-66cm2

G, the Newtonian constant of gravitation, is G, therefore, is equal to 6.67876984 x 10-11m3Kg-1sec-2. This compares to the currently measured value of 6.67(+0.1,-0.01) x 10-11m3Kg-1sec-2. 1

 

STUDY DESCRIPTION

      In the paradigm the agents' states are called states of information. This information paradigm is the most useful in formulating a theory of consciousness. The conditions under which an agent is conscious of information from one or more of its states of information are given below.

       Each agent is in one of two states with regard to each of its states of information (relation), either a state of denial of that information state or a state of non-denial of that information state, which of the two being determined (made to be so) by the agent itself. That the agent determines its own states of denial and non denial of its own information states is what is meant by the agent's individual initiative or ability.

       Each of an agent's information states is based on the entire domain of a particular agent, which consists of the qualities of that particular agent, its information states, and its self-determined states of denial or non denial with regard to its information states. In Diagram 2, agent A has three information states because in this example three agents exist: A, W, and I. Agent A is in a state of non-denial of its information state based on agent W, a state of denial of its information state based on itself, and a state of denial of its information state based on agent I (the denied information states are crossed out). The qualities of each of the agents are summarized as 'an existence who (the particular agent: A, W, or I) determines' (See the Diagram below.)


On the above Diagram 2 the domain of agent A is presented.

       In order for an agent to be in a conscious state, the agent must be in a state of non-denial of at least one of its information states. An agent in a self-determined state of non-denial of a state of information based on a particular agent is conscious of any information in that information state that is based on a quality of the particular agent that is the same as any of the original agent's own qualities. Consciousness is a nonphysical agent's state of the sameness of not-denied information with some aspect of itself. For example, if agent A is in a state of non-denial of its information state based on itself, agent A is conscious of the information in that state that is based on all three of agent A's qualities: intrinsic uniqueness (whoness), individual initiative (ability), and existence. In other words, agent A is conscious of its own existence as the particular nonphysical agent that it is. If, alternatively, agent A is in a state of non-denial of its state of information based on some other agent, say agent W, agent A is conscious of the information in that state that is based on agent W's existence quality, which is the same as agent A's own existence quality, but not of the information based on agent W's qualities of whoness and ability, because who agent W is is not the same as who agent A is, and agent W's ability is not the same ability as agent A's ability (see Diagram 3).5 Consciousness of existence without whoness and ability is consciousness of physical existence; agent A is conscious of a physical entity. A nonphysical agent's state of the sameness of not-denied information based on the existence quality of an agent other than itself with its own existence quality is consciousness of a physical entity. We call this simplest type of physical entity a proto-fermion.6 (Diagram 3 and future diagrams do not show any denied information states in an agent's domain because they do not contribute to the agent's consciousness.)

THE DOMAIN OF AGENT A


Diagram 3

       Due to the fact that an agent's information state of the domain of a particular agent contains information based on that particular agent's denied and not-denied information states, an agent in a state of non-denial of an information state may be conscious of information based on qualities of agents other than the particular agent on whom the information state is based. For example, if agent A is in a state of non-denial of its information state based on agent W, and agent W is in a state of non-denial of its information state based on agent I (in labeled directed graph notation, AàWàI), agent A is conscious of its information based on agent I's existence quality in addition to its information based on agent W's existence quality.  Agent A is conscious of two proto-fermions. How two or more proto-fermions are physically (temporally, spatially, energetically) related in an agent's state of consciousness depends on the configuration of the system of agents in not-denied information states on which that conscious state is based.

        In AàWàI, agent W, like agent A, is conscious of a proto-fermion due to the sameness of agent I's existence quality with its own existence quality. This is an example of a 'baby' common universe. If the average number of not-denied information states per agent is more than two, directed graph theory predicts the existence of a giant system of agents in not-denied information states that includes most of the agents.

       Such a giant system is the basis of the individual conscious state of each of the agents in it. shows (a) a toy model (or baby-universe) of a giant system patterned on the giant system on which our universe is based and (b) the same system re-drawn to emphasize the largest circuit-type arrangement in that system. The absence of an arrow from one agent to another means that the corresponding information state is denied.


Diagram 4. a


Diagram 4. b

     Each agent in or connecting into the circuit has an individual state of consciousness of a physical universe that is the same as every other agent's, except that each agent's viewpoint differs according to that agent's position in the giant system. Thus the agents seem to themselves to be conscious of an independently existing physical universe.

        In this information paradigm, we, the reader, the writers, and all other individuals that can be conscious, are the nonphysical agents, rather than being bodies, conscious minds, or even physically located view point souls. A nonphysical agent is not ordinarily conscious of itself as nonphysical because it is ordinarily in a state of denial of its information state of itself, and is therefore only conscious of it self by means of a circuit arrangement. If this is the case, the nonphysical agent is conscious of itself as an intrinsically unique entity with individual initiative that is physically related to physical entities


Click on the picture for bigger view, then again click to zoom it
or right click to download it.

       The matrix formalism as and addition to the graph formalism, introduced and developed by Biljana Percinkova, is presented on the Diagram above. Percinkova has also developed different algorithms for finding specific sub-graphs and structures of interest in particle physics.

PERCINKOVA’S ALGORITHM FOR FINDING PROTO-PHENOMENA IN ONE UNIT

1-D SPACE CONTINUUM ARRANGEMENT

     The following algorithm has been proposed by Prof. Biljana Percinkova:

    The matrix could be used for finding many (if not all) combinations of proto-phenomena since it is just another view of the graphs, only spread out in plane.

      I’ve found an algorithm for discovering all the structures of Linear plus Bifurcated type of combination forming space-continuum between units of matter. The "lists" in this mini-spanning trees are one unit of 1-D space from the root. The discovering of the structures is done in systematic way, so that no sub-structures are missed. This is like Mendeleev System of elements.

  •  From the row I proto-fermions F, O, Z, P are one unit 1-D space from W through I.

      First the ones  (1-s) in the row are found. Then a(i,j) cell, being one from the central circuit (the Hamiltonian) is marked as reference cell; in this case it is the cell ((I,F). Then its origin is being determined from the (i-1) row, in this case the W row; that is the cell (W,I). Finally the (j-1) column is being checked – in this case this the I column for finding other possible roots for the sub-structures, denoted with ones in the column.

      (Beautiful synchronicity has happened. Namely, when starting the research I've commenced with the L row having E P R as its members so nicely pointing to Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen experiment; this experiment is my favorite and mentioned in Henry Stapp's writings.)

 Hence we have:

            W
           

          I
          ↓  ↓  ↓  ↓

           
F  O  Z  P

  • From the row F proto-fermions X, Y are one unit 1-D space from I through F.

I                            N
         ↓                           ↓               
         F                           F
         ↓  ↓                       ↓  ↓
         X Y                       X  Y
 

  • From the row F proto-fermions E, M, T  are one unit 1-D space from F through Y.

F
          ↓
          Y
          ↓  ↓  ↓
          E M T 

  • From the row E proto-fermions Q, L are one unit 1-D space from Y through E. Checking (j-1) column, in this case E column, two other sub-structures (1-s in that column) are being discovered. Here we have L being 1-D space from itself L (L à E à L):

    Y                 L                 K
    ↓                 ↓                 ↓
    E                 E                 E
    ↓  ↓              ↓  ↓              ↓  ↓
    Q L              Q L              Q L 

  • From the row Q proto-fermions M, H are one unit 1-D space from E through Q.

E

Q
↓  ↓
M H
 

  • From the row M proto-fermions O, R are one unit 1-D space from Q through M. (O and R are 1-s in the M row; the cell (M,O) is referential (a(i,j)). The origin a(i-1, j-1) is the cell ((Q,M) showing the space distance from Q through M. Finally the (j-1) column, the M column is being checked for other roots: these are Y and D.

   Q                 Y                  D
   ↓                  ↓                  ↓
   M                 M                 M
   ↓  ↓              ↓  ↓              ↓  ↓
   O R             O R              O R
 

  • From the row N proto-fermions I, O, Z are one unit 1-D space from B through N.

B

N
↓  ↓  ↓
I   O Z
 

  • From the row X proto-fermions L, V are one unit 1-D space from Z through X; the column X gives additional sub-structure.

    Z                 F
    ↓                 ↓
    X                 X
    ↓  ↓              ↓  ↓
    L  V             L  V
 

  • From the row L proto-fermions E, P, R are one unit 1-D space from X through L. The column L, being (j-1),  gives additional sub-structure. Here we have E being one unit 1-D space from itself ! (E à L à E).

X                 E
↓                 ↓
L                 L
↓  ↓  ↓          ↓  ↓  ↓
E  P R         E  P R 

  • From the row C proto-fermions T, U are one unit 1-D space from P through C, cell (P,C).

    P
    ↓
    C
    ↓  ↓
    T U 
 

  •  From the row D proto-fermions W, M, R are one unit 1-D space from T through D, cell (T,D).

T
          ↓
          D
          ↓  ↓  ↓
          W M R
 

  • From the row G proto-fermions B, V are one unit 1-D space from R through G, cell (R,G).

R
          ↓
          G
          ↓  ↓
          B V

 

Connectedness of a random directed graph, digraph, as seen by Baker and Szekeres:

It is as if we are dealing with the following situation:

      There are N labeled individuals (i1 to iN ). In an arbitrary sequence one individual chooses to be in a state of knowledge of another individual. We may say that at knowledge choice number q, individual i chooses to be in a state of knowledge of individual j (i à j, i ≠ j). This situation is a random labeled digraph, where the number q of directed edges increases with each knowledge choice made.

        We can also write i àà j (i precedes j, or i is connected to j) if there is a set of knowledge choices (directed edges) (i1 = i à i2 ), (i2à i3) ,...., (ip–1 à ip = j) linking i to j. We can say that the individuals are (the graph is) totally connected at knowledge choice q if i àà j for all ordered pairs of individuals i, j (i ≠ j).

i ~àà j indicates that i is not connected to j, and i ~à j indicates that i does not choose to be in a state of knowledge of j.

       At knowledge choice q let c(q) be the total number of ordered pairs of individuals i, j such that i àà j. The individuals will be totally connected at knowledge choice q if c(q) = N (N – 1). That is every individual is connected to every other individual. We can describe the connectedness of the individuals (digraph) to be given by a parameter:

x(q) = 0 ≤ x(q) ≤ 1

       The total number of connections c(q) can be broken down into two parts. Let cd(q) be the number of ordered pairs of individuals i, j such that the knowledge choice i à j is the first knowledge choice for which i àà j. We call cd(q) the number of direct connections. Let ci(q) be the number of ordered pairs of individuals i,j such that i ~à j until after the first knowledge choice for which i àà j. We call ci(q) the number of indirect connections.

c(q) = cd(q) + ci(q)

      We can describe the direct connectedness and indirect connectedness of the individuals (graph) to be given by xd(q) and xi(q) respectively where:

xd(q) = ; xi(q)= ; x(q) = xd(q) + xi(q)

      How do x(q), xd(q), and xi(q) vary with the number of knowledge choices? Clearly monotonically. We can derive differential equations that describe the average growth of c(q), cd(q) and ci(q) as follows:

For each i let:

d(i,q) be the number of individuals k such that k àà i, which is the number who are connected to i.

For each j let:

e(j, q) be the number of individuals l such that j àà l, which is the number to whom j is connected.

At knowledge choice q suppose that i à j. Then how many new connections of the form k àà l are established?

Clearly if i àà j before knowledge choice q, the probability of which is x(q) , then no new connections are established. That is:

c(q + 1 ) = c(q) ; cd(q + 1 ) = cd(q); ci(q + 1 ) = ci(q)

      However if i ~àà j at knowledge choice q, the probability of which is 1 – x(q), then not only is the new direct connection i à j established but also the indirect connections k àà l, such that k àà i, j àà l and k ~àà l. [D. Perhaps this should read, not k~àà l, but kààj and iààl.]

Let the number that are already connected at knowledge choice q be f (i,j,q).

      There will also be extra connections due to those that j is connected to that i is not connected to, and due to those that are connected to i that are not connected to j. Let their numbers be:

g(i,j,q) = number of l such that j àà l & i ~àà l

and

h(i,j,q) = number of k such that k àà i & k ~àà j

So in this case:

 cd(q + 1) = cd(q) + 1

ci(q + 1) = ci(q) + d(i,q) e(j,q) – f(i,j,q)+ g(i,j,q) + h(i,j,q)

c(q + 1) = c(q) + 1 + d(i,q) e(j,q) – f(i,j,q) + g(i,j,q) + h(i,j,q)

Given the relative probabilities of the two cases:

cd (q + 1) = x(q) cd(q) + {1 – x(q)} {cd(q) + 1}

= cd(q) + {1 – x (q)} ...................................(1)

ci(q + 1) = x(q) ci(q) + {1 – x(q)} {ci(q) + d(i,q) e(j,q) – f(i,j,q) + q(i,j,q) + h(i,j,q)}

= ci(q) + {1 – x(q)} {d(i,q) e(j,q) – f(i,j,q) + g(i,j,q) + h(i,j,q)}

c(q + 1) = c(q) +{1– x(q)} { 1 + d(i,q) e(j,q) – f(i,j,q) + g(i,j,q) + h(i,j,q) }

The probability at knowledge choice q of i àà j is x(q). This applies equally to all pairs so we may estimate:

d(i,q) = e(j,q) = x(q) (N – 1)

f(i,j,q) = d(i,q) e(j,q) x(q) = x(q)3 (N – 1)2

g(i,j,q) = e(j,q) x(q) = x(q)2 (N – 1)

h(i,j,q) = d(i,q) x(q) = x(q)2 (N – 1)

So we can estimate:

ci(q + 1) – ci(q) + {1 – x(q) } { x(q)2 (N – 1)2 – x(q)3 (N – 1)2 + 2 x(q)2 (N – 1)}

= ci(q) + x(q)2 {1 – x(q)} (N – 1) [N { 1 – x(q)}+ {1+ x (q) } ]

 xi (q + 1 ) = xi(q) + x(q)2 { 1 – x(q) } [ { 1 – x (q) } + { 1 + x(q) } / N ]

From equation (1) we can see:

xd (q + 1) = xd (q) + { 1 – x(q) } / { N (N – 1)

For N large we may approximate:

xd(q + 1 ) = xd(q) + {1 – x(q) } / N2

xi(q + 1 ) = xi(q) + x(q)2 { 1 – x(q)}2

Replacing the difference equations by differential equations:

dxd/dq = (1 – x) / N2 .....................................(2)

dxi /dq = x2(1 – x)2 .......................................(3)

dx/dq = (1 – x) / N2+ x2 (1 – x)2 ...............(4)

Equation (4) can be replaced by two differential equations, the first for x à 1 and the second for x2 (1 – x) > 1 / N2 .

For x << 1 we may replace (1 – x ) by 1 and get:

dx/dq = 1 / N2 + x2 = (1 + N2 x2) / N2 .....(5)

This differential equation is readily solved:

q = N arctan(N x) + constant

At q = 0, x = 0, so constant = 0, and:

q = N arctan(N x) ............................................(6)

x = (1 / N) tan(q / N) ....................(7)

For x << 1 we also have from equation (2):

dxd/dq = 1 / N2.

xd = q / N2 + constant

At q = 0, xd = 0, so constant = 0, and:

xd = q / N2 ........................................................(8)

 … xi = (1 / N) { tan(q / N) – (q / N) } ........(9)

For x2 (1 – x) > 1 / N2 we can ignore (1 – x) / N2 and get from equation (4):

dx/dq = x2 (1 – x)2 .......................................(10)

The errors involved in making the approximations for the differential equations (5) and (10), e1 and e2 respectively, are:

e1 = – (x / N2+ x4)

e2 = (1 – x ) N2

The differential equations (5) and (10) are equally in error when:

| e1| = | e2 |

x / N2 + x = ( 1 – x ) / N2

Comments on connectedness of a random digraph 

(1.....)

       The expected proportion of individuals who have not made a knowledge choice to be in  a state of knowledge of another individual by knowledge choice q is exp( – q/N).  The proportion of individuals who have not become known by any individual (i.e. no individual has made a choice to be in a state of knowledge of them) by knowledge choice q is also exp( – q/N).  Consequently, by knowledge choice q, 1 – exp( – q/N) individuals have made a knowledge choice and 1 – exp(– q/N) individuals have become known.  The maximum number of connections c(q) will occur when all individuals who have made a knowledge choice are connected to all individuals who have become known. So the maximum connectivity that is possible by knowledge choice q is  

x ≤ {1 – exp(– q/N)}2.

         At q = (1 + π/2) N there will be about 8% of individuals who have not made a knowledge choice.  This means that x can be no more than 0.85 at this point, which is at variance with x = 1 near (1 + π/2) N.  It can also be shown that the last individual is likely to make its first knowledge choice or the last individual will become known when q = log(4 N). In other words the connections cannot be complete until about q = log(4 N) .

       It seems likely that the reason for this discrepancy is that no account was taken above of the numbers of individuals who have not made a knowledge choice and have not become known as a function of q.  The problem arises due to using x as an average connectivity when the underlying distribution is skewed due to the Poisson distribution of knowledge choices.

 

The Origin of Time - Charles Berner:

         Agents in not-denied information states are the basis of an agent's conscious experience of the passage of time. There is no background of time (or space) against which the agents exist. There is not a blankness or nothing, or any other state, that 'precedes' or 'follows' their existence. The agents do not exist at a certain time, remain the same over time, or change. All of this is also true of the agents' self-determined states of denial and non-denial. Each agent determines which denial and non-denial states it is in, and the determinations of all of the agents decide the form of each agent's conscious experience, including each agent's consciousness of the passage of time.  

         Diagram 5 shows the states of consciousness produced by the arrangement of agents in not-denied information states A à W à I, and Diagram 6 concentrates on agent A's state of consciousness, which is consciousness of the passage of time. In Diagrams 5 and 6, and in the explanatory text following them, the non-directed graph symbol called a vertex (a dot) placed next to a letter representing an agent indicates that some agent is conscious of that agent as a physical particle. For example, in the arrangement A àà I•, agent A is conscious of two proto-fermions, W• and I• ; agent W is conscious of one proto-fermion, I•; and agent I is not conscious of any proto-fermions. Labeling proto-fermions with the letter representing the agent on whom they are based is for ease of explanation only, because 'who determines' is not included in an agent's consciousness of a proto-fermion. An agent only distinguishes proto-fermions by their physical characteristics, which are determined by the arrangement that is the basis of the agent's conscious state.

          If an agent is conscious, that consciousness is always a single state of consciousness, because the agent is a single individual, although there may be many sub-states of consciousness embedded within that single state of consciousness. In Diagrams 5 and 6, agent A is in a single state of consciousness (based on the entire arrangement A àà I•) in which there is an embedded state of consciousness (based on the sub arrangement A à W•). The embedded state is a state of the sameness of agent A's information based on agent W's existence quality with agent A's own existence quality, i.e., a state of consciousness of a proto fermion based on agent W (labeled W•) . The single state consists of that embedded consciousness of W• plus a state of the sameness of agent A's information based on agent I's existence quality with agent A's existence quality, i.e., consciousness of I•.

     However, the consciousness of I• is contingent on the existence of the sub-arrangement (A à W•) that is the basis of the embedded consciousness of W• ; therefore, in agent A's single state of consciousness, I•'s existence is contingent on W• ' s existence. This contingency is experienced by agent A as temporal: W• existed before I•. Thus agent A's single state of consciousness is agent A's present moment in which I• exists, and the embedded state of consciousness is agent A's memory, also in that present moment, of a 'past' moment in which W• existed. Because the contingency is asymmetric, agent A is conscious of time as passing in one direction only, and because agent A's conscious experience is a single state, the passage of time of which agent A is conscious is a time continuum. The continuum of time in this example is bounded by the non-durational past instant of time in which W• existed, and by the non-durational present instant of time in which I• exists.


Diagram 5

          An individual state of consciousness is produced for an agent for each sub-arrangement beginning with that agent, and these individual states are all embedded in the agent's single state of consciousness based on the entire arrangement. An arrangement is defined as a directionally connected series of agents in not-denied information states. If one or more of the agents in the arrangement are in more than one not-denied information state, the arrangement is a furcated, or branched


Diagram 6

        One or more conscious states being embedded in another conscious state is a conscious comparison of the states, or an observation of a physical relationship between proto-fermions, or an observation of a protoboson.

        For example, the consciousness that agent A has of a time continuum relating the two proto-fermions W• and I• is an observation of a proto-time boson, a 'message carrier' of the temporal relationship between the two proto-fermions. In the next section, in which space is modeled, space is shown to be derivative on time, therefore a spatial relationship is also a type of boson. Then, finally, an energy boson, the photon, is modeled and shown to be derivative on space-time. In the above examples there is no spatial or energy relationship between any of the proto-fermions.

         A comparison of one or more observations is a measurement. For example, if there is the arrangement A à àà F•, the sub-arrangement A àà I•, producing an observation for agent A of a time continuum, is embedded in and thereby compared to agent A's single state of observation of the entire time continuum based on the entire arrangement. This comparison is a measurement of the entire time continuum using the embedded time continuum as a measuring rod. If the duration of the embedded time continuum is called one time quantum (1 tq), the entire time continuum is of 2 tq duration. In agent A's consciousness of that bounded time continuum there are no breaks or parts; therefore, it is a true continuum in the Aristotelian sense. A time continuum is not composed of time quanta, a time continuum is only measured in time quanta. A future does not appear in the consciousness of agents and thus has no physical reality. The future is only a possibility.

  Space

       The linear embedding of one or more conscious states in one conscious state is conscious observation of a time continuum. Conscious observation of a space continuum, which is based on a furcated arrangement, is the non-linear embedding of two or more linear embeddings (or observations of time continua) in one conscious state.

Agent W's conscious observation of a space continuum is diagrammed below.

      
Diagram 7

  In Diagram 7, agent W's conscious state based on sub-arrangement W à I• is linearly embedded in agent W's conscious state based on sub-arrangement W àà F• and it is also linearly embedded in agent W's conscious state based on sub-arrangement W àà Z•. These two conscious observations of time continua are non-linearly embedded in agent W's single state of consciousness based on the entire arrangement. The non-linear embedding, or comparison, of the two observations of time continua is a measurement of the two time continua, each against the other. In agent W's single state of consciousness, the two different time continua have the same duration, therefore proto-fermions F• and Z• are consciously experienced by agent W to be two different proto-fermions that exist at the same time. This is observation of a one-dimensional (1-D) space continuum bounded by F• and Z•. Because each time continuum acts as the standard of measurement for the other time continuum, the extent of the 1-D space continuum is one quantum of length, 1 lq. The non-directed graph symbol called an edge (a line) is drawn between F• and Z• in Diagram 7, to illustrate the bounded 1-D space continuum. F• and Z• are true point fermions; like electrons and quarks, they do not extend in space.

        In agent W's conscious memory of I•, I• is not located in space, and agent W is not conscious of itself at all.

        In the following arrangement, agent W is conscious of five proto-fermions, four of which are located in bounded 3-D space. If more arrows extended from agent I, agent W's consciousness would include additional spatial dimensions up to N-l, where N is the total number of agents that exist. In our current universe, however, a circuit arrangement results in consciousness of spatial dimensions being limited to three because any spatial dimensions in excess of three are consciously experienced by the agents in the circuit as quickly decaying into energy.

        In the Graphs A, B, C and D in the proceedings different aspects of the Radical Theory are given:


Diagram A


Diagram B


Diagram C


Diagram D

CONCLUSION

     The Information (or Lila ) Paradigm is a radical theory of the reality behind some of the most important phenomena in physics and artificial intelligence introduced by Charles Berner and mathematically supported by Biljana Percinkova, Michael Baker and Peter Szekeres. It is offering a new vision of physical reality enabling us to resolve some of the main barriers known in contemporary Quantum Mechanics and Artificial Intelligence, such as the collapse/observer problem or Gödel’s Theorem of Incompleteness. Strong scientific support as comparison of the parameters obtained with the values measured in CERN institute for Particle Physics is provided, as in the example given below:

 


   
 


 

 



 
 
Home  |   About Us  |   Support 
Copyright ฎ 2007 www.seeu.edu.mk   design by m.apostolova@seeu.edu.mk